Jump to content

Perception: Difference between revisions

m
Grammar edits and last refined alterations
m (Reference added)
m (Grammar edits and last refined alterations)
Line 6: Line 6:


=== Introduction ===
=== Introduction ===
Perception is the sensory experience of the world<ref name="ref1"/>, the process and the subjective result of obtaining and processing information from stimuli originated in the environment and the self. Yet every individual may perceive the same situation differently, which is filtered by biological mechanisms, personal beliefs, and cultural contexts. What we perceive may be far from a direct reflection of reality. Personal interpretation is further influenced by cultural or ideological circumstances, effecting individual worldviews consistently.<ref name="ref2"/> Whether through vision, touch, hearing, taste, or smell, the human perception is never purely objective. For this reason, philosophical approaches question how each person's subjective pattern recognition relate to any objective reality. Consequently, examining both the neuroscience of sensation and the philosophical implications of our perceptual construction of the world, broadens our understanding of implicit and explicit frameworks of reality.
Perception is the sensory experience of the world<ref name="ref1"/>, the process and the subjective result of obtaining and processing information from stimuli originated in the environment and the self. Yet every individual may perceive the same situation differently, which is filtered by biological mechanisms, personal beliefs, and cultural contexts. What we perceive may be far from a direct reflection of reality. Personal interpretation is further influenced by cultural or ideological circumstances, affecting individual worldviews consistently.<ref name="ref2"/> Whether through vision, touch, hearing, taste, or smell, human perception is never purely objective. For this reason, philosophical approaches question how each person's subjective pattern recognition relates to any objective reality. Consequently, examining both the neuroscience of sensation and the philosophical implications of our perceptual construction of the world broadens our understanding of implicit and explicit frameworks of reality.
== Neuroscientific Foundations of Perception ==
== Neuroscientific Foundations of Perception ==


=== Visual Perception ===
=== Visual Perception ===
Visual perception can be understood as a diverse process that begins with the transformation of light stimuli into meaningful cognitive interpretations involving retinal sensing through photoreceptors and cortical processing in multiple brain areas.<ref name=":0">Donato, R., Pavan, A., & Campana, G. (2020). Investigating the Interaction Between Form and Motion Processing: A Review of Basic Research and Clinical Evidence. ''Frontiers in Psychology'', ''11''. <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.566848</nowiki></ref> The photoreceptors receive light signals through the retina, converting them into electrical signals. Those signals are then transmitted along the optic nerve in the eye, in order to reach the lateral geniculate nucleus before arriving at the striate cortex. This cortex, known as the visual cortex serves on fundamental basis for the conscious perception of static form and local brightness differences, establishing the base for more complex visual processing.<ref>Pollen, D. A. (1999). On the Neural Correlates of Visual Perception. ''Cerebral Cortex'', ''9''(1), 4–19. <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/9.1.4</nowiki></ref> Following that, after leaving the visual cortex, signals travel along the dorsal stream to the parietal cortex, serving for spatial orientation and motor actions such as reaching or eye movements. Further, focusing on forms, colours and object identity, signals must flow through the ventral stream into the inferior temporal cortex.<ref name=":0" /> For perceptual experience to arise, the visual cortex engages in recursive feedback loops with higher brain regions, for instance temporal and parietal. Those feedbacks enter into loops between each other to continuously compare new sensory data with prior knowledge or expectations, leading to our visual recognition of the outer world.<ref name=":0" /> Along with Descartes analytical approach, raw light signals are simplified into features such as edges and movements by the visual cortex, then recombined under guidance of attention and memory. This creates a synergy between modern neuroscience and analysing complex phenomena into smaller bits.<ref name=":6">Noller, F. (2021). ''Information Processing''. Glossalab. <nowiki>https://www.glossalab.org/wiki/Processing_of_information,_building_of_truth</nowiki></ref>  
Visual perception can be understood as a diverse process that begins with the transformation of light stimuli into meaningful cognitive interpretations involving retinal sensing through photoreceptors and cortical processing in multiple brain areas.<ref name=":0">Donato, R., Pavan, A., & Campana, G. (2020). Investigating the Interaction Between Form and Motion Processing: A Review of Basic Research and Clinical Evidence. ''Frontiers in Psychology'', ''11''. <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.566848</nowiki></ref> The photoreceptors receive light signals through the retina, converting them into electrical signals. Those signals are then transmitted along the optic nerve in the eye in order to reach the lateral geniculate nucleus before arriving at the striate cortex. This cortex, known as the visual cortex, serves as a fundamental basis for the conscious perception of static form and local brightness differences, establishing the base for more complex visual processing.<ref>Pollen, D. A. (1999). On the Neural Correlates of Visual Perception. ''Cerebral Cortex'', ''9''(1), 4–19. <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/9.1.4</nowiki></ref> Following that, after leaving the visual cortex, signals travel along the dorsal stream to the parietal cortex, serving for spatial orientation and motor actions such as reaching or eye movements. Further, focusing on forms, colours, and object identity, signals must flow through the ventral stream into the inferior temporal cortex.<ref name=":0" /> For perceptual experience to arise, the visual cortex engages in recursive feedback loops with higher brain regions, for instance, temporal and parietal. Those feedbacks enter into loops between each other to continuously compare new sensory data with prior knowledge or expectations, leading to our visual recognition of the outer world.<ref name=":0" /> Along with Descartes analytical approach, raw light signals are simplified into features such as edges and movements by the visual cortex, then recombined under the guidance of attention and memory. This creates a synergy between modern neuroscience and analysing complex phenomena into smaller bits.<ref name=":6">Noller, F. (2021). ''Information Processing''. Glossalab. <nowiki>https://www.glossalab.org/wiki/Processing_of_information,_building_of_truth</nowiki></ref>  


Moreover, visual perception involves actively searching for relevant stimuli, influenced by external factors such as color salience and movement, as well as internal states in order to recognise objects. For instance, conspicuous features can capture human attention instantly, leading to unusual preferences when distractions occur. At this state, the ventral stream captures specific details from it. In addition, the temporal cortex stores those representations, helping humans to categorise and label familiar objects in fractions of a second.<ref name=":1">Jansson-Boyd, C. V., & Bright, P. (2024). Visual neuroscience. ''Elsevier EBooks'', 51–69. <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1016/b978-0-443-13581-1.00004-2</nowiki></ref> Furthermore, visual search engages emotional and reward circuits, when identifying form and motion. The ventral tegmental area and nucleus accumbens interact with cortical regions to process rewarding stimuli, reinforcing behaviour patterns triggered by appealing elements. Likewise research shows, that emotional associations are carried firmly throughout visual perception, that bias us towards or against objects before consciously registering the object. This phenomenon, known as microvalence, refers to subconscious evaluation of an object's aversiveness during visual processing.<ref name=":1" />
Moreover, visual perception involves actively searching for relevant stimuli, influenced by external factors such as colour salience and movement, as well as internal states in order to recognise objects. For instance, conspicuous features can capture human attention instantly, leading to unusual preferences when distractions occur. At this stage, the ventral stream captures specific details from it. In addition, the temporal cortex stores those representations, helping humans to categorise and label familiar objects in fractions of a second.<ref name=":1">Jansson-Boyd, C. V., & Bright, P. (2024). Visual neuroscience. ''Elsevier EBooks'', 51–69. <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1016/b978-0-443-13581-1.00004-2</nowiki></ref> Furthermore, visual search engages emotional and reward circuits when identifying form and motion. The ventral tegmental area and nucleus accumbens interact with cortical regions to process rewarding stimuli, reinforcing behaviour patterns triggered by appealing elements. Likewise, research shows that emotional associations are carried firmly throughout visual perception, which biases us towards or against objects before we consciously register the object. This phenomenon, known as microvalence, refers to subconscious evaluation of an object's aversiveness during visual processing.<ref name=":1" />


=== Haptic Perception ===
=== Haptic Perception ===
Touch helps us to navigate through the physical space, by integrating information from the skin, muscles and joints to foster a cohesive perception of objects, surfaces and spatial relationships. While joints and muscles enables feedback about cup's orientation and weight, the skin contains a complex system of specialised nerve endings designed to detect mechanical stimuli such as pressure, vibration, and texture.<ref name=":02">Reed, Catherine L., and Mounia Ziat. “Haptic Perception: From the Skin to the Brain ☆.” ''Reference Module in Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Psychology'', 2018, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1016/b978-0-12-809324-5.03182-5</nowiki>.</ref> The majority of receptors, which are distributed throughout the layers of the skin, are represented by:
Touch helps us to navigate through the physical space by integrating information from the skin, muscles, and joints to foster a cohesive perception of objects, surfaces, and spatial relationships. While joints and muscles enable feedback about an object's orientation and weight, the skin contains a complex system of specialised nerve endings designed to detect mechanical stimuli such as pressure, vibration, and texture.<ref name=":02">Reed, Catherine L., and Mounia Ziat. “Haptic Perception: From the Skin to the Brain ☆.” ''Reference Module in Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Psychology'', 2018, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1016/b978-0-12-809324-5.03182-5</nowiki>.</ref> The majority of receptors, which are distributed throughout the layers of the skin, are represented by:


# Merkel's Disc's:
# Merkel's Disc's:
Line 22: Line 22:
# Hair Follicle Receptors:
# Hair Follicle Receptors:
#* Responding to bending or subtle movement of hair
#* Responding to bending or subtle movement of hair
#* Detection of gentle stimuli (e.g. a soft breeze)  
#* Detection of gentle stimuli (e.g., a soft breeze)
# Mechanoreceptors:
# Mechanoreceptors:
#* Meissner's Corpuscles: Specialise in detecting fine precise touch and are concentrated in the fingertips
#* Meissner's Corpuscles: Specialise in detecting fine, precise touch and are concentrated in the fingertips
#* Pacinian Corpuscles: Respond to deep pressure and vibration regards sudden changes in pressure
#* Pacinian Corpuscles: Respond to deep pressure and vibration regarding sudden changes in pressure
#* Ruffini's Endings: Perceives sustained pressure and skin stretch, helping to maintain a firm grip on objects
#* Ruffini's Endings: Perceives sustained pressure and skin stretch, helping to maintain a firm grip on objects


At different rates of stimulation each of the receptor types adapts continuously.<ref>Andrade, Maria, et al. “The Senses 4: Touch – Physiology of the Sensation and Perception of Touch | Nursing Times.” ''Nursing Times'', 13 Dec. 2022, www.nursingtimes.net/neurology/the-senses-4-touch-physiology-of-the-sensation-and-perception-of-touch-13-12-2022/.</ref> Likewise it converts physical energy (pressure, vibration, temperature) into electrical impulses, which are send along nerve fibers towards the spinal cord ensuring instantaneous awareness of haptic changes.<ref>Blumenrath, Sandra . “The Neuroscience of Touch and Pain.” ''Www.brainfacts.org'', 3 Feb. 2020, www.brainfacts.org/thinking-sensing-and-behaving/touch/2020/the-neuroscience-of-touch-and-pain-013020.</ref> The electrical impulses are either transmitted through slowly adapting fibers, firing with persistent pressure, or rapidly adapting fibers. Once triggered, these signal travel to the somatosensory cortex, containing topographic maps of the skin, which represents different body parts.<ref name=":02" />
At different rates of stimulation, each of the receptor types adapts continuously.<ref>Andrade, Maria, et al. “The Senses 4: Touch – Physiology of the Sensation and Perception of Touch | Nursing Times.” ''Nursing Times'', 13 Dec. 2022, www.nursingtimes.net/neurology/the-senses-4-touch-physiology-of-the-sensation-and-perception-of-touch-13-12-2022/.</ref> Likewise, it converts physical energy (pressure, vibration, temperature) into electrical impulses, which are sent along nerve fibres towards the spinal cord, ensuring instantaneous awareness of haptic changes.<ref>Blumenrath, Sandra . “The Neuroscience of Touch and Pain.” ''Www.brainfacts.org'', 3 Feb. 2020, www.brainfacts.org/thinking-sensing-and-behaving/touch/2020/the-neuroscience-of-touch-and-pain-013020.</ref> The electrical impulses are either transmitted through slowly adapting fibres, firing with persistent pressure, or rapidly adapting fibers. Once triggered, these signals travel to the somatosensory cortex, containing topographic maps of the skin, which represent different body parts.<ref name=":02" />


Furthermore, heating or cooling are detected by skin thermoreceptors influencing our recognition of objects (e.g metal feels colder than plastic at room temperature). If an object begins to warm up or cool down in the hand, through feedback humans can then indicate material properties such as moisture. This overall process from touching to interpretation follows multiple pathways. First of all the skin collects input with receptors (touch and vibration). Further, it lead's to an awareness of the object's movement in order to judge its weight and orientation, which is defined as kinaesthetic feedback. This refers to the sense of limb movement, where muscles, tendons, and joints work together with inputs to inform the brain. Those informations are then processed at the cortex and other parietal regions. Consequently, the multiple lines of sensory information offer a detailed and adaptive representation of the physical world.<ref name=":02" />
Furthermore, heating or cooling are detected by skin thermoreceptors influencing our recognition of objects (e.g., metal feels colder than plastic at room temperature). If an object begins to warm up or cool down in the hand, through feedback humans can then indicate material properties such as moisture. This overall process from touching to interpretation follows multiple pathways. First of all, the skin collects input with receptors (touch and vibration). Further, it leads to an awareness of the object's movement in order to judge its weight and orientation, which is defined as kinaesthetic feedback. This refers to the sense of limb movement, where muscles, tendons, and joints work together with inputs to inform the brain. Those informations are then processed at the cortex and other parietal regions. Consequently, the multiple lines of sensory information offer a detailed and adaptive representation of the physical world.<ref name=":02" />


=== Auditory Perception ===
=== Auditory Perception ===
The interpretation of sound, begins with sound waves defined as vibration through a medium, for instance air pressure, which travales through the outer ear channels towards the eardrum. The eardrums begin to vibrate and convey them through the middle ear bones into the fluid-filled cochlea of the inner ear. Further, the frequency being established in the basilar membrane of the cochlea disperse it to specific locations, forming a tonotopic map. Hair cells convert these mechanical vibrations into neural signals transmitted onwards the auditory nerve to the brain. However, due to fine arranged cochlear filters a vast range of sound frequencies can be detected and separated into distinct pitches.<ref name=":2">Oxenham, Andrew J. “How We Hear: The Perception and Neural Coding of Sound.” ''Annual Review of Psychology'', vol. 69, no. 1, 4 Jan. 2018, pp. 27–50, www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5819010/, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-122216-011635</nowiki>.</ref> Once the signals travel through the central auditory nerve, main sound properties such as amplitude and frequency are processed by the midbrain's inferior colliculus, while high frequency is received by the inferior colliculus, overlapping with pure auditory processing. However, before tactile high frequencies reach the inferior colliculus, they must pass through the pacinian corpuscles of the skin. Pacinian corpuscles are primarily touch receptors contributing to a better sound experience. This overall convergence suggests, that touch and sound information being shared thereby interchangeable neuronal circuits, being the reason therefore why we feel and hear music. This underlines the human capacity to distinguish numerous pitches due to the cochlea's ability to segregate frequencies precisely.<ref name=":2" /> In the same way, hearing a sound from different angles illustrates how inductive reasoning shapes the confidence we have in locating a pitch, leading to a overcross of auditory sensationa and perceptual belief.<ref name=":6" />
The interpretation of sound begins with sound waves defined as vibrations through a medium, for instance, air pressure, which travels through the outer ear channels towards the eardrum. The eardrums begin to vibrate and convey them through the middle ear bones into the fluid-filled cochlea of the inner ear. Further, the frequency being established in the basilar membrane of the cochlea disperses it to specific locations, forming a tonotopic map. Hair cells convert these mechanical vibrations into neural signals transmitted onwards the auditory nerve to the brain. However, due to finely arranged cochlear filters, a vast range of sound frequencies can be detected and separated into distinct pitches.<ref name=":2">Oxenham, Andrew J. “How We Hear: The Perception and Neural Coding of Sound.” ''Annual Review of Psychology'', vol. 69, no. 1, 4 Jan. 2018, pp. 27–50, www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5819010/, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-122216-011635</nowiki>.</ref> Once the signals travel through the central auditory nerve, main sound properties such as amplitude and frequency are processed by the midbrain's inferior colliculus, while high frequency is received by the inferior colliculus, overlapping with pure auditory processing. However, before tactile high frequencies reach the inferior colliculus, they must pass through the pacinian corpuscles of the skin. Pacinian corpuscles are primarily touch receptors contributing to a better sound experience. This overall convergence suggests that touch and sound information being shared, thereby interchangeable neuronal circuits, being the reason therefore why we feel and hear music. This underlines the human capacity to distinguish numerous pitches due to the cochlea's ability to segregate frequencies precisely.<ref name=":2" /> In the same way, hearing a sound from different angles illustrates how inductive reasoning shapes the confidence we have in locating a pitch, leading to an overcross of auditory sensation and perceptual belief.<ref name=":6" />


=== Smell Perception ===
=== Smell Perception ===
Generally speaking, perceiving smell begins in the nose, where specialised olfactory receptors bind molecules. Correspondingly, humans posses approximately 396 functional receptor genes and many pseudogenes. These genes encode a large family of proteins found on the surface of cells. As a result of encoding these G protein-coupled receptors, cells can respond to thousands of potential molecules entering our nasal cavity. This binding creates an electrical signal to the transmitted to the olfactory bulb, where subtle scent differences are distinguished.<ref>Sharma, Anju, et al. “Sense of Smell: Structural, Functional, Mechanistic Advancements and Challenges in Human Olfactory Research.” ''Current Neuropharmacology'', vol. 17, no. 9, 22 Aug. 2019, pp. 891–911, www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7052838/, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.2174/1570159x17666181206095626</nowiki>.</ref>  
Generally speaking, perceiving smell begins in the nose, where specialised olfactory receptors bind molecules. Correspondingly, humans possess approximately 396 functional receptor genes and many pseudogenes. These genes encode a large family of proteins found on the surface of cells. As a result of encoding these G protein-coupled receptors, cells can respond to thousands of potential molecules entering our nasal cavity. This binding creates an electrical signal that is transmitted to the olfactory bulb, where subtle scent differences are distinguished.<ref>Sharma, Anju, et al. “Sense of Smell: Structural, Functional, Mechanistic Advancements and Challenges in Human Olfactory Research.” ''Current Neuropharmacology'', vol. 17, no. 9, 22 Aug. 2019, pp. 891–911, www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7052838/, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.2174/1570159x17666181206095626</nowiki>.</ref>  


After initial processing in the olfactory bulb, those information are passed to the piriform cortex region, where odor identification occurs, while on the other hand the amygdala and hippocampus receive likewise signals. The amygdala and hippocampus link smells to emotions and memories, contributing additional to an experience of recollections.<ref>NeuroLaunch editorial team. “Brain and Smell: Exploring the Olfactory System’s Neural Pathways.” ''NeuroLaunch.com'', 30 Sept. 2024, neurolaunch.com/what-part-of-the-brain-controls-smell/.</ref>  
After initial processing in the olfactory bulb, that information is passed to the piriform cortex region, where odour identification occurs, while on the other hand the amygdala and hippocampus receive similar signals. The amygdala and hippocampus link smells to emotions and memories, contributing additionally to an experience of recollections.<ref>NeuroLaunch editorial team. “Brain and Smell: Exploring the Olfactory System’s Neural Pathways.” ''NeuroLaunch.com'', 30 Sept. 2024, neurolaunch.com/what-part-of-the-brain-controls-smell/.</ref>  


Moreover, research suggest that the right orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) is essential for consicous olfactory awareness. As depicted in a case, individuals with damage to the right OFC can partially response to smell, while being unaware of it. Even though, odor processing occurs at the piriform cortex or left OFC, a full smell perception requires the connectivity of all involved brain regions.<ref>Li, Wen, et al. “Right Orbitofrontal Cortex Mediates Conscious Olfactory Perception.” ''Psychological Science'', vol. 21, no. 10, 3 Sept. 2010, pp. 1454–1463, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797610382121</nowiki>.</ref> Nevertheless, the interplay between smell, memory and emotion is profound, hence it can evoke memories and shape our affective mood.
Moreover, research suggests that the right orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) is essential for conscious olfactory awareness. As depicted in a case, individuals with damage to the right OFC can partially respond to smell while being unaware of it. Even though odour processing occurs at the piriform cortex or left OFC, a full smell perception requires the connectivity of all involved brain regions.<ref>Li, Wen, et al. “Right Orbitofrontal Cortex Mediates Conscious Olfactory Perception.” ''Psychological Science'', vol. 21, no. 10, 3 Sept. 2010, pp. 1454–1463, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797610382121</nowiki>.</ref> Nevertheless, the interplay between smell, memory, and emotion is profound, hence it can evoke memories and shape our affective mood.


=== Taste Perception ===
=== Taste Perception ===
The idea of taste starts with taste visual buds found in across the tongue's surface - called papillae, where each bud contains receptor cells, supporting cells, and basal cells.<ref>Henley, Casey. “Taste.” ''Openbooks.lib.msu.edu'', Michigan State University Libraries, 1 Jan. 2021, openbooks.lib.msu.edu/neuroscience/chapter/taste/.</ref> Flavour such as sugars or bitter alkaloids are detected by those cells and converted into electrical signals. The signals are then transmitted via the cranial nerves to the brainstem and thalamus before reaching the primary gustatory cortex, where flavour information is perceived and processed.<ref>team, NeuroLaunch editorial. “Brain’s Taste Control Center: Mapping the Neural Pathways of Flavor Perception.” ''NeuroLaunch.com'', 30 Sept. 2024, neurolaunch.com/what-part-of-the-brain-controls-taste/. Accessed 29 Dec. 2024.</ref>  
The idea of taste starts with taste visual buds found across the tongue's surface—called papillae, where each bud contains receptor cells, supporting cells, and basal cells.<ref>Henley, Casey. “Taste.” ''Openbooks.lib.msu.edu'', Michigan State University Libraries, 1 Jan. 2021, openbooks.lib.msu.edu/neuroscience/chapter/taste/.</ref> Flavours such as sugars or bitter alkaloids are detected by those cells and converted into electrical signals. The signals are then transmitted via the cranial nerves to the brainstem and thalamus before reaching the primary gustatory cortex, where flavour information is perceived and processed.<ref>team, NeuroLaunch editorial. “Brain’s Taste Control Center: Mapping the Neural Pathways of Flavor Perception.” ''NeuroLaunch.com'', 30 Sept. 2024, neurolaunch.com/what-part-of-the-brain-controls-taste/. Accessed 29 Dec. 2024.</ref>  


Besides the gustatory cortex, taste, smell, and texture are as well processed by the orbitofrontal cortex, influencing decisions about consume behaviour. In comparison, certain tastes evoke memories being attributable to the amygdala, while the hypothalamus contributes by regulating appetite and taste preferences. However, flavour depends, as a research depicts, further from genetics, aging, and neurological conditions. This underlies that the function of taste involves numerous neural circuits ensuring that each bite resonates beyond the tongue.<ref>Trivedi, Bijal P. “Neuroscience: Hardwired for Taste.” ''Nature'', vol. 486, no. 7403, June 2012, pp. S7–S9, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1038/486s7a</nowiki>.</ref>
Besides the gustatory cortex, taste, smell, and texture are also processed by the orbitofrontal cortex, influencing decisions about consumption behaviour. In comparison, certain tastes evoke memories being attributable to the amygdala, while the hypothalamus contributes by regulating appetite and taste preferences. However, flavour depends, as research depicts, further from genetics, ageing, and neurological conditions. This underlies that the function of taste involves numerous neural circuits ensuring that each bite resonates beyond the tongue.<ref>Trivedi, Bijal P. “Neuroscience: Hardwired for Taste.” ''Nature'', vol. 486, no. 7403, June 2012, pp. S7–S9, <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1038/486s7a</nowiki>.</ref>


== Philosophical Dimensions of Perception ==
== Philosophical Dimensions of Perception ==


=== Dualism ===
=== Dualism ===
Dualism proposes that perceiving is not a one dimensional outcome of physical processes in the brain, rather it involves a separate mental dimension which shapes our conscious experience. Accordingly the idea of Descartes argues that the mind is indeed a thinking substance distinct from the body's extended substance. This aligns with Plato's views where the soul is held to be immaterial and intellectually with higher being forms.<ref name=":5" /> While eyes, ears, and other organs receive physical data, our conscious perception exceeds these signals, and being therefore accountable for our intentional and subjective interpretation within our mental realm. For this reason, the dualism claims that physical explanations cannot resolve the pure nature of sensory experience. For instance, when viewing a striking painting, the sensation is tangled to the subjective awareness in a way, where no objective, third-person description of the painting's properties could evoke the same experience. Therefore, if mental events were only based on physical circumstances, then anyone using the right instruments could equally observe, yet first-person experiences resist sich observations. Nonetheless, whether the mental district is a separated substance or not, dualism demands that understanding true perception requires more than physical causation alone.<ref name=":5">Robinson, Howard. “Dualism.” ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', 2020, plato.stanford.edu/entries/dualism/.</ref>
Dualism proposes that perceiving is not a one-dimensional outcome of physical processes in the brain, rather, it involves a separate mental dimension that shapes our conscious experience. Accordingly, the idea of Descartes argues that the mind is indeed a thinking substance distinct from the body's extended substance. This aligns with Plato's views, where the soul is held to be immaterial and intellectually with higher being forms.<ref name=":5" /> While eyes, ears, and other organs receive physical data, our conscious perception exceeds these signals, and we are therefore accountable for our intentional and subjective interpretation within our mental realm. For this reason, the dualism claims that physical explanations cannot resolve the pure nature of sensory experience. For instance, when viewing a striking painting, the sensation is tangled to the subjective awareness in a way where no objective, third-person description of the painting's properties could evoke the same experience. Therefore, if mental events were only based on physical circumstances, then anyone using the right instruments could equally observe, yet first-person experiences resist such observations. Nonetheless, whether the mental district is a separated substance or not, dualism demands that understanding true perception requires more than physical causation alone.<ref name=":5">Robinson, Howard. “Dualism.” ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', 2020, plato.stanford.edu/entries/dualism/.</ref>


=== The Causal Theory ===
=== The Causal Theory ===
Perception requires a casual link between an external object and perceiver's sensory experience following the causal theory. We see, hear or smell an object, if that object itself brings the relevant sensory experiences. This principle can be illustrated by the thought experiment, were a blocked pathway (e.g., a mirror) exits in front of the person and the pillar behind the person, no direct causal relationship exists and therefore the pillar cannot be truly perceived. In this scenario, the mirror redirects the light from the actual pillar to the eyes, and therefore can the individual not perceive the intended object. Likewise suggested by Hyman, a person lacks true perception, if the external object is not causing the experience. This applies across modalities of vision, auditory, and olfaction for intuitive judgement in "Blocker cases" (e.g., a mirror redirecting) and "Non-Blocker cases" (e.g., brain stimulation producing similar experience). However, some individuals diverge form those intuitive philosophical standpoints, where participants believe that genuinely perception can occur even in Non-Blocker scenarios, as shown by studies.<ref>Roberts, P., Allen, K. & Schmidtke, K. Reflective Intuitions about the Causal Theory of Perception across Sensory Modalities. ''Rev.Phil.Psych.'' '''12''', 257–277 (2021). <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00478-6</nowiki></ref> This discrepancy raises questions about whether causal condition is truly a conceptial truth for perception. Thereupon, this mismatch illustrates that individuals assume perception might be conceivable only on brain stimulation, implying an exposure without physical obstruction.   
Perception requires a causal link between an external object and the perceiver's sensory experience following the causal theory. We see, hear, or smell an object if that object itself brings the relevant sensory experiences. This principle can be illustrated by the thought experiment where a blocked pathway (e.g., a mirror) exists in front of the person and the pillar behind the person, no direct causal relationship exists, and therefore the pillar cannot be truly perceived. In this scenario, the mirror redirects the light from the actual pillar to the eyes, and therefore the individual cannot perceive the intended object. Likewise suggested by Hyman, a person lacks true perception if the external object is not causing the experience. This applies across modalities of vision, auditory, and olfaction for intuitive judgement in "Blocker cases" (e.g., a mirror redirecting) and "Non-Blocker cases" (e.g., brain stimulation producing similar experience). However, some individuals diverge from those intuitive philosophical standpoints, where participants believe that genuine perception can occur even in non-Blocker scenarios, as shown by studies.<ref>Roberts, P., Allen, K. & Schmidtke, K. Reflective Intuitions about the Causal Theory of Perception across Sensory Modalities. ''Rev.Phil.Psych.'' '''12''', 257–277 (2021). <nowiki>https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00478-6</nowiki></ref> This discrepancy raises questions about whether causal condition is truly a conceptual truth for perception. Thereupon, this mismatch illustrates that individuals assume perception might be conceivable only on brain stimulation, implying an exposure without physical obstruction.   


In contrast, due to the causal condition embedded in our very own concept of perception, deeper reflection or strict philosophical training is needed to align our intuitions with the standards of the causal theory. Nonetheless, in order to avoid illusions or blocked pathways, it is necessary to identify, if the external cause matches the internal impression.<ref name=":6" />  
In contrast, due to the causal condition embedded in our very own concept of perception, deeper reflection or strict philosophical training is needed to align our intuitions with the standards of the causal theory. Nonetheless, in order to avoid illusions or blocked pathways, it is necessary to identify if the external cause matches the internal impression.<ref name=":6" />  


=== Direct Realism ===
=== Direct Realism ===
Direct realism suggests that the perception of objects such as chairs, sun, or cups of coffee, arises from our engagement with them, rather than mere mental images. A sensible idea for this implies that objects exist independently of any perceiver's awareness. Hence, direct realism can be divided into naïve realism and scientific realism. According to naïve realism, objects retain all perceived properties, for example colour or surface texture regardless of the observation. In contrast, scientific realism argues that certain examined qualities (e.g., sweetness) depend on the examiner, while mass or shape persist irrespective of observation. Likewise, Locke's notion of primary (e.g, size, motion) versus secondary (e.g., colour, taste) qualities aligns partially, whereas primary exists objectively and secondary dispositional. However, both assert fundamentally that the senses must be in direct contact with the external reality.<ref name=":4">O’Brien, Daniel. “Perception, Objects of | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.” ''Objects of Perception'', iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H1.</ref>
Direct realism suggests that the perception of objects such as chairs, books, or cups of coffee arises from our engagement with them, rather than mere mental images. A sensible idea for this implies that objects exist independently of any perceiver's awareness. Hence, direct realism can be divided into naïve realism and scientific realism. According to naïve realism, objects retain all perceived properties, for example, colour or surface texture, regardless of the observation. In contrast, scientific realism argues that certain examined qualities (e.g., sweetness) depend on the examiner, while mass or shape persist irrespective of observation. Likewise, Locke's notion of primary (e.g., size, motion) versus secondary (e.g., colour, taste) qualities aligns partially, whereas primary exists objectively and secondary dispositional. However, both assert fundamentally that the senses must be in direct contact with the external reality.<ref name=":4">O’Brien, Daniel. “Perception, Objects of | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.” ''Objects of Perception'', iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H1.</ref>


=== Indirect Realism ===
=== Indirect Realism ===
Indirect realism states that physical objects exist mind-independently, and we therefore perceive them through an internal intermediary rather than directly. This construct (intermediary), acts as a bridge between the mind and the external world. For instance, a chair is an internally produced image in the human visual system caused by the physical properties (light reflection, etc.), rather than a physcial entity itself.<ref name=":4" /> Hence, these physical objects and their properties cause mental perceptions, being commonly termed with sense data (e.g., colour, texture, shape). Despite being caused by physical stimuli, these sensed data are not themselves physical. According to John Locke, we do not perceive an external object itself but rather our idea of it, reinforcing this idea of an intermediary.<ref name="ref14" /> <ref name="ref13" /> Thus, the mind indirectly perceives an object thorugh sense data, which is generated in part by a causal chain including light rays, neuronal processes, and the subjective experience of colour, shape, or other features.<ref name=":4" /> As a result, the real object (e.g., a chair) remains independent of the observer, while our knowledge of the external world exists constantly indirect.
Indirect realism states that physical objects exist mind-independently, and we therefore perceive them through an internal intermediary rather than directly. This construct (intermediary) acts as a bridge between the mind and the external world. For instance, a chair is an internally produced image in the human visual system caused by the physical properties (light reflection, etc.), rather than a physical entity itself.<ref name=":4" /> Hence, these physical objects and their properties cause mental perceptions, being commonly termed with sense data (e.g., colour, texture, shape). Despite being caused by physical stimuli, these sensed data are not themselves physical. According to John Locke, we do not perceive an external object itself but rather our idea of it, reinforcing this idea of an intermediary.<ref name="ref14" /> <ref name="ref13" /> Thus, the mind indirectly perceives an object through sense data, which is generated in part by a causal chain including light rays, neuronal processes, and the subjective experience of colour, shape, or other features.<ref name=":4" /> As a result, the real object (e.g., a chair) remains independent of the observer, while our knowledge of the external world exists constantly indirect.


=== The Intentional Theory ===
=== The Intentional Theory ===
Perception is a representational relationship linking conscious experience to the external world in virtue of their content rather than any direct sensory object following the intentional theory.<ref name=":4" /> However, we perceive a chair not by apprehending a mental entity, but by adopting a perceptual state which posses intentional content. This suggests that our perceptual state inherently carry representations (e.g., there is a chair) that manifest the existence of objects within our mind. Therefore, seeing a bent stick in water is experienced still as a "bent stick", despite that the stick might be straight in the physical reality. Likewise, those illusions demonstrate cases where the world is misaligned with the mind's interpretation, yet the representational object remains intact within the human.<ref>Mcintyre, Ronald, and David Woodruff Smith. ''Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook''. Original, 1989.https://www.csun.edu/~vcoao087/pubs/intent.pdf</ref> Moreover, when referring to intentionality, perception is defined to resembling beliefs or other attitudes, which postulates that illusions involve representational states that fail to match external objects or their properties. This concludes, that they not require the postulation of mental intermediaries, for example sense data.<ref name=":4" />
Perception is a representational relationship linking conscious experience to the external world in virtue of their content rather than any direct sensory object following the intentional theory.<ref name=":4" /> However, we perceive a chair not by apprehending a mental entity, but by adopting a perceptual state that possess intentional content. This suggests that our perceptual state inherently carries representations (e.g., there is a chair) that manifest the existence of objects within our mind. Therefore, seeing a bent stick in water is experienced still as a bent stick despite the fact that the stick might be straight in the physical reality. Likewise, those illusions demonstrate cases where the world is misaligned with the mind's interpretation, yet the representational object remains intact within the human.<ref>Mcintyre, Ronald, and David Woodruff Smith. ''Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook''. Original, 1989.https://www.csun.edu/~vcoao087/pubs/intent.pdf</ref> Moreover, when referring to intentionality, perception is defined as resembling beliefs or other attitudes, which postulates that illusions involve representational states that fail to match external objects or their properties. This concludes that intentionalism does not require not the postulation of mental intermediaries, for instance, sense data.<ref name=":4" />


=== The Disjunctive Theory ===
=== The Disjunctive Theory ===
A sensible idea for this theory is its core distinction between the veridical (mind-independent object) and non-veridical (illusion or hallucination) perception. The veridical states that the human observe a mind-independent object in the world (e.g, a real cup in front you) involving the actual external object, whereas non-veridical defines illusory or hallucinatory experiences as not genuinely seeing a mind-independent object. For this reason, J.M. Hinton argued that veridical perception and hallucination do not need to share a common nature, implying that even when both are indistinguishable from the inside, they do not share identical intrinsic properties.<ref>Soteriou, M. (2009). ''The Disjunctive Theory of Perception (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)''. Stanford.edu. <nowiki>https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-disjunctive/</nowiki></ref> In contrast, intentionalism proposes that both those experiences share an internal representations of which one happens to match reality, while disjunctive theory denies a shared mental representation for both experiences. Hence, seeing a cup in front of oneself, the cup belongs partly to the perceptual state, because its properties create in part the nature of one's perception. Whereas in hallucination, there does not exist such real cup forming a part of the experience. This difference is displayed by disjunctivism, either seeing actually a cup, where the external object is present, or merely undergoing an hallucination being entirely internal and absent from the real object.<ref name=":4" /> Thereupon, disjunctivism embraces a form of externalism, stating that identical brain states alone cannot guarantee the same perceptual state, due to the veridical experience that involves an actual object in the presence to be experienced. This stems that, if the neural processes remain the same while observing the object, but the external object disappears (e.g., a person shifts to a hallucination), the mental state changes from the ground on, once the subject is no longer the same type of the perceptual state. Thus, both veridical and non-veridical do not share an internal representation.<ref name=":4" />
A sensible idea for this theory is its core distinction between the veridical (mind-independent object) and non-veridical (illusion or hallucination) perception. The veridical states that the human observes a mind-independent object in the world (e.g., a real cup in front of you) involving the actual external object, whereas non-veridical defines illusory or hallucinatory experiences as not genuinely seeing a mind-independent object. For this reason, J.M. Hinton argued that veridical perception and hallucination do not need to share a common nature, implying that even when both are indistinguishable from the inside, they do not share identical intrinsic properties.<ref>Soteriou, M. (2009). ''The Disjunctive Theory of Perception (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)''. Stanford.edu. <nowiki>https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-disjunctive/</nowiki></ref> In contrast, intentionalism proposes that both those experiences share an internal representation of which one happens to match reality, while disjunctive theory denies a shared mental representation for both experiences. Hence, seeing a cup in front of oneself, the cup belongs partly to the perceptual state, because its properties create in part the nature of one's perception. Whereas in hallucination, there does not exist such a real cup forming a part of the experience. This difference is displayed by disjunctivism, either seeing actually a cup, where the external object is present, or merely undergoing a hallucination, being entirely internal and absent from the real object.<ref name=":4" /> Thereupon, disjunctivism embraces a form of externalism, stating that identical brain states alone cannot guarantee the same perceptual state, due to the veridical experience that involves an actual object in the presence to be experienced.   If the neural processes remain the same while observing the object, but the external object disappears (e.g., a person shifts to a hallucination), the mental state changes from the ground on, once the subject is no longer the same type of the perceptual state. Thus, both veridical and non-veridical do not share an internal representation.<ref name=":4" />
=== Beholder's Share ===
=== Beholder's Share ===
The Beholder's Share, first introduced by Alois Riegl, later elaborated by Ernst Gombrich, highlights how each viewer actively completes an artwork. Sensory elements such as colours, patterns, shapes or scenic details initially shape our perception of the piece. However, top down processes, like prior expectations or learned associations, further refine our conscious vision. Certainty, perception involves the interpretation and integration of sensory stimuli and expectations, unlike sensing relying only on raw detection of stimuli.<ref name=":3">Seth AK. From Unconscious Inference to the Beholder’s Share: Predictive Perception and Human Experience. ''European Review''. 2019;27(3):378-410. doi:10.1017/S1062798719000061</ref> For this reason, can perception be seen as an active construction of experience, while sensing as a passive reception of information. Due to the heavy influential nature of context, information about the artist's life or familiarity with their work of art can dramatically shift interpretation, illustrating that viewer's knowledge and beliefs co-create an artwork's effect. Moreover, the artist's intentions often differ from those of the observer. This lack or conflict of context can completely redirect the emotional or intellectual experience of an artwork. Following this interplay between stimulus input and the observer's framework undermines the deeper principle, that perception emphasises a projection of one's internal model onto the external features to construct meaning.<ref name=":3" /> As a result, the physical properties of the artwork itself emerge as much as from the viewer's interpretive engagement.
The Beholder's Share, first introduced by Alois Riegl, later elaborated by Ernst Gombrich, highlights how each viewer actively completes an artwork. Sensory elements such as colours, patterns, shapes, or scenic details initially shape our perception of the piece. However, top-down processes, like prior expectations or learnt associations, further refine our conscious vision. Certainty, perception involves the interpretation and integration of sensory stimuli and expectations, unlike sensing relying only on raw detection of stimuli.<ref name=":3">Seth AK. From Unconscious Inference to the Beholder’s Share: Predictive Perception and Human Experience. ''European Review''. 2019;27(3):378-410. doi:10.1017/S1062798719000061</ref> For this reason, can perception be seen as an active construction of experience, while sensing as a passive reception of information. Due to the heavily influential nature of context, information about the artist's life or familiarity with their work of art can dramatically shift interpretation, illustrating that the viewer's knowledge and beliefs co-create an artwork's effect. Moreover, the artist's intentions often differ from those of the observer. This lack or conflict of context can completely redirect the emotional or intellectual experience of an artwork. Following this interplay between stimulus input and the observer's framework undermines the deeper principle that perception emphasises a projection of one's internal model onto the external features to construct meaning.<ref name=":3" /> As a result, the physical properties of the artwork itself emerge as much from the viewer's interpretive engagement.


== Broader Influences of Perception ==
== Broader Influences of Perception ==